Thursday 27 August 2020

Scientific Theory and Lived Experience

In 1927, astronomer George Lemaître published a paper which pointed out that, when applied to the universe as a whole, Einstein’s General Relativistic field equations have no static solutions: either the universe is expanding or else it is collapsing (Lemaître 1927).  Einstein himself found this conclusion unsatisfactory, so he modified his equations to include a term – the ‘cosmological constant’ – that would counter-balance any potential expansion or contraction, thereby producing a model of a fixed universe with no beginning or end (Einstein 1931).  In 1929, the astronomer Edwin Hubble presented observations confirming that the universe is indeed expanding (Hubble 1929), as predicted by the original equations of General Relativity, leading Einstein to eventually call the cosmological constant his 'biggest blunder.'  Had Einstein, instead, trusted and followed his equations, he could have been the first to predict the expansion of the universe and, by running things backward, the Big Bang itself.  (Note: currently, the effect of dark matter on the universe is thought, by some, to be well accounted for by the reintroduction of the cosmological constant, though not to counter-balance expansion but to accelerate it; so the expansionary implications of General Relativity would still have been rightly predicted by Einstein had he stuck to his equations).   

Einstein also resisted another implication of his theory: that a sufficiently massive body would collapse to a point of infinite density creating a bottomless well in spacetime from which nothing could escape, now commonly known as a black hole.  Einstein disliked the idea, which represented a discontinuity in the fabric of spacetime, so he worked to discover some mechanism that would de facto prevent matter from collapsing to such a point:

 

The “Schwarzschild singularity” [i.e. black hole] does not appear for the reason that matter cannot be concentrated arbitrarily. And this is due to the fact that otherwise the constituting particles would reach the velocity of light. (Einstein 1939, p. 936)

 

In other words, a black hole is impossible because it would require matter to violate an ironclad implication of Special Relativity: nothing can accelerate to the speed of light.  This, however, turns out to be untrue (i.e. it does not require such acceleration), and today black holes are regularly detected by astronomers.  Once again, Einstein would have been well advised to have trusted his equations.

 

A similar conflict between mathematics and physical intuition befalls anyone who attempts to understand quantum mechanics, which entails that physical systems are regularly in a state of superposition.  Superposition is almost impossible to interpret physically because it represents a system as being distributed between discrete states; e.g. a particle is both in position p1 and position p2.  All the same, superposition is mathematically straightforward and can be used to make extremely precise predictions.  As it turns out, quantum mechanics is generally regarded as the most predictively successful theory of all time (Lewis 2016).  Accordingly, if we follow the math, even without understanding its physical significance, then we can predict which states of a physical system will be observed and when.  

 

These cases are illustrative.  When even a great thinker’s philosophical or commonsensical beliefs conflict with counterintuitive laws of nature (mathematically described), the latter often emerge victorious and have done so on historically significant occasions.  There is no reason to doubt that Einstein’s commitments to both a steady-state and continuous universe were sincere and grounded in serious reflection.  Still, he was wrong; here are examples in which the greatest scientist in human history, reflecting on his own greatest achievement, was led astray by his philosophical commitments about the nature of reality as a whole.  All of this is a bit surprising.  After all, it was Einstein who, correctly, insisted that we reject what experience tells us about the nature of space, time, and motion in favour of his Relativistic equations.

 

In classical phenomenology, stemming from Husserl, ‘lived experience’ is experience as one finds it.  Attending to lived experience, then, is paying attention to one’s experiences as they are, without the influence of interpretation or theory. But, of course, it is everyone’s lived experience that time and space are absolute (the same for everyone everywhere), immutable (unaffected by matter or events), and distinct (one can move back and forth in space but not time).  Nevertheless, Einstein's theories entail that space and time vary by frame of reference, are altered by matter and gravity, and are mathematically connected components of a four-dimensional whole.  Einstein’s conclusions have been empirically confirmed.  For example, if one were to construct a GPS system without employing his equations, one would be left with unusable devices – one needs to account for the ways in which space and time vary with speed and gravity in order to pinpoint a precise location on a map using trilateration from known satellite positions.  Importantly, this does not change the experience of space and time.  Spacetime impacts us psychologically just as it did prior to Einstein, seeming to split into two distinct, unchanging, and universal measures.  All the same, we now know this experience to be a poor guide to the nature of space and time themselves.  

 

If one takes a look up at the darkened sky, night after night, what one sees is effectively unchanged; there is certainly no experience of space itself expanding.  But experience is a poor guide here; space is not only expanding in all directions but is accelerating outward, as noted above.  Even Einstein was misled. 

 

In a post-Darwinian world, it should not surprise us that there might exist some conflict between common sense, philosophical commitments, or lived experience, on the one hand, and the laws of nature, on the other.  We now know that human beings are the products of nature: we have evolved through a process of variation, selection, and inheritance that favours traits that contribute to the production of offspring that survive to reproductive maturity.  This is how we came to be what we are.  It is entirely possible, accordingly, that certain cognitive shortcuts have been favored by evolution because they help, or at least fail to hinder, reproductive success by conferring advantages, such as energy efficiency or simplicity, if not accuracy.  These shortcuts could, for example, lead us to find it instinctive to view the world a certain way – there is an evolutionary advantage, or lack of harm, in doing so – even though this way of seeing things obscures certain details, or applies in only local or special cases.  We should not, in other words, presume that natural cognitive strategies will be fully generalizable because they developed as solutions to local problems.

 

What is surprising is that we are, somehow, able to learn some fully generalizable laws.  We could very well have evolved without any capacity to know the large-scale features of reality, just as other creatures – fish, bears, beetles – have in fact done.  We somehow managed the trick, however, and we can be confident in this because of the surprising predictive successes of theories such as Einstein’s General Relativity and quantum mechanics.  We would have little reason to suppose that human reason could extend beyond the local conditions under which it evolved were it not for cases such as these where mathematical formalism, often not easily interpreted, leads to surprising predictions that are confirmed, repeatedly and to high degrees of precision.  Somehow, the mind is able to construct models that apply everywhere and every-when, even though the brain itself evolved under spatiotemporally limited pressures.  While we don’t know how this happened, we can hazard some guesses.  For example, whichever features of the universe are truly universal will thereby hold in any local conditions under which human beings faced evolutionary challenges and may leave their mark there.  Hence, a sufficiently sophisticated cognitive organ, forged by evolutionary forces in a local environment, could pick up the scent of the universal; human brains might have evolved a mechanism for detecting subtle but available imprints of large-scale structure that, when combined with the ability to generalize and extrapolate, allow us to posit universal laws that can be tested observationally.  We currently do not know the actual story, but something like this is clearly possible, for we regularly predict with success, at least in the natural sciences.

 

All the same, that our evolved heuristics might have built-in blind spots with regard to the large-scale structure of reality is not surprising; perhaps it is to be expected.  We should not, however, lose sight of the fact that such blind spots might equally well exist with regard to the inner world of thought and experience.  The brain, like other evolved organs, has its limits, and our knowledge of any part of the world is dependent on its scope, power, and resolution.  There is little reason to suppose that the scope is limitless, the power infinite, the resolution perfect.  Much as the eye is not naturally able to see itself, or the tongue to taste itself, it may be that the brain is not well-evolved to know itself.  Various aspects of the inner workings of our own cognitive system may, in other words, be as hidden or counterintuitive as the outer workings of spacetime; the brain is, after all, a natural system too.  What is delivered to the mind by reflection on our own cognition and experiences may mislead, just as happened to Einstein when he reflected on his experience of the universe as a whole.  The brain, being a physical system, may have structural features that escape what the it itself evolved to deliver to reflection, which historically needed to be focused on what is most essential for survival and reproduction.  It may, of course, be possible to overcome some cognitive limitations by pooling resources (linking brains together), inventing new instruments of investigation (MRIs), and the careful use of experiment, observation, and analysis; we can, by comparison, use tools such as mirrors to allow they eye to see itself.  But there is no particularly good reason to suppose that the immediate, unreflective impressions delivered by a mind about itself should have some unrevisable character, especially when up against well confirmed scientific models.  Perhaps thinking about thinking is infallible; perhaps the experience of experience is incorrigible; but, then again, perhaps not.  Maybe, when reflecting on itself, the mind relies on evolved heuristics that are subject to biases similar to those that impact the reflection on our experience of space, time, and motion.  Without evidence for the infallibility or incorrigibility of the cognitive organ's operations on itself  there is no way to know that lived experience is reliably informative, even about experience.  

 

If this weren’t true, i.e. if our minds were completely and invariably self-transparent, then there would hardly be any need for the various disciplines – psychology, psychiatry, social work, etc. – that constitute modern psychotherapy.  We know, however, that many, if not all, of us sometimes require the assistance of a trained outsider to truly understand what is going on within.  Even if some aspects of self-reflection are infallible, it is clear from the legitimate need for psychotherapeutic professionals that not all of it is.  The deeply held deliverances of reflection on inner experience are not guaranteed to be correct.  Lived experience may very well matter, and deserve to be attended to, but it hardly amounts to a trump card against amassed scientific evidence.

 

There is more to say, of course, but I will come back to further issues in another post.


References

Einstein, A.: 1931, ‘Zum kosmologischen Problem der allgemeinen Relativitätstheorie’,

Sitzungsberichte der Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, Physikalisch-mathematische Klasse, pp. 235–237

Einstein, A.: 1939, ‘On a Stationary System With Spherical Symmetry Consisting of Many Gravitating Masses’, Annals of Mathematics, Second Series, 40: pp. 922-936

Hubble, E.: 1929, ‘A Relation between Distance and Radial Velocity among Extra-Galactic Nebulae’. Proc. Nat. Acad. Sci. 15: pp. 168-73

Lemaître, G.: 1927, Discussion sur l'évolution de l'univers

Lewis, P. J.: 2016, Quantum Ontology: A Guide to the Metaphysics of Quantum Mechanics, Oxford University Press.

 

Wednesday 20 May 2020

In Defence of Inefficiency

Sitting at home during a state of semi-quarantine makes it hard to resist commenting on the overall situation.  Much – perhaps too much – has already been written about COVID-19 but one thing that has stood out to me, and that has not received much comment, is this: the pandemic demonstrates that, as a matter of fact, a certain amount of economic inefficiency is a good, possibly even necessary, thing.

I live in Canada, which is the 10th largest economy in the world (according to worldometer we are just behind Italy and a bit ahead of Russia).  Less than 30 minutes to my south lies the United States of America, the largest economy in the world, not to mention the most powerful nation our planet has ever seen.  Nonetheless, when the pandemic reached ‘social distancing’ proportions, neither country had anything approaching enough face shields, masks, ventilators, or hospital beds, all of which quickly fell into critical shortages.  A month later, and neither country was able to procure ‘personal protective equipment’ or ventilators in anything approaching sufficient numbers.  In fact, at one point Canada was trying to import large numbers of surgical masks from China, to whom it had donated a few months earlier (the shipment had to be rejected as improperly made).  Now, more than two months in, and the situation is largely unchanged, though less critical thanks to social distancing having managed to ‘flatten the curve’, i.e. slow the inevitable spread of the disease so that the limited resources can handle the rate of new infection.

So, why are nations whose deeply integrated economies comprise over 25% of the world’s GDP (26.12% according to worldometer) but whose populations add up to less than 5% of the world’s total (4.73% according to worldometer), utterly unable to produce such simple products as masks and face shields in the face of the largest public health crisis in decades?  What is going on here?

There are probably dozens of contributing factors, of course, but one of them is, I think, connected to our nearly obsessive concern with efficiency in modern politics and economics.  To begin, notice that the reason why Canada has been unable to ramp up its manufacture of medical supplies is that most manufacturing is not done here.  In the past, nations basically did everything they could to produce what they needed themselves.  Today, things are different.  A country, such as Canada, is just one stop in a large, global supply and manufacture chain that is mostly located outside of its borders.  Natural resources are extracted from A, shipped to B for refinement, moved to C for processing, then on to D for shaping into parts, and finally to E for assembly into final products.  No country has control over the whole thing, so no country can simply ramp up as it sees fit – it must put its order in and then wait for it to move down the chain and for products to move back up again.

Knowing this, why can’t Canada stock up and have large storehouses of material in waiting at any given time to be put to use?  Well, this is where I see the emphasis on efficiency playing a key role.  It would be politically difficult to sell a budget that dedicated hundreds of millions, if not billions, of dollars to the purchase and storage of material that will simply sit, unused, until a future time that nobody can see coming.  That would be a waste of money that could go to other, more pressing, concerns.  Further, the emphasis on efficiency probably asserts itself at every stage of the supply and manufacture chain: factories don’t make extra products just in case they are ordered – they wait for the orders to come in, and then order the parts, after which the part manufacturer orders the processed material, which triggers an order for refined material, which causes an order for natural resource extraction.  At each stage, there will be financial pressure and incentive to avoid excess production that sits around waiting.  The end result is a chain of supply and manufacture that works smoothly and quickly when all is going well, but is not positioned to absorb shocks because it lacks room to maneuver.  

So, a country such as Canada ramp up production because it does not control the manufacturing process, which is run as close to the bone as possible, so that it cannot ramp up very easily anyway.  Further, political pressure makes it hard for a government to justify spending on unused stockpiles.  Add it all up, and when a pandemic hits, a country such as Canada isn't able to respond as needed.

Notice, however, that evolution through natural selection has, in many cases, seen the problem and responded.  For example, though human beings can get along fine with one hand, one ear, one eye, one kidney, and so on, we are typically born with two (unfortunately only one heart, brain and pancreas – I guess there are limits to Mother Nature’s generosity).  This is obviously inefficient.  We would require fewer calories if we only had one of everything.  Still, I am happy for the wisdom of evolution, for it is often good to have a backup, even when it costs something.  I always, for instance, spend money on an external hard drive in addition to the one in my computer so that I can have a second copy of all my files.  

Having backups, stockpiles, alternatives, etc., is of great use in times of crisis.  It is okay to be inefficient by having unused oversupply because it may be just the thing that saves you from a worse outcome when trouble arrives, which it always does and always unpredictably – I have no plans to ever lose an eye, but if it comes to that it is of great comfort that I will still be able to see, if less fully.  Governments ought to view stockpiles of crisis-ready supplies in the same way: hopefully they will never be needed, but they should still be there.  Short of repatriating manufacturing, that seems like the only thing to do.  It might cost a bit more, but right now, it sure seems worth it.  

Monday 11 May 2020

Empiricism and Standpoint Epistemology

In an interesting blog post, Liam Kofi Bright argues that standpoint epistemology is implied by the basic commitments of empiricism.  In what follows, I argue that this is an error.
Kofi Bright’s characterization of standpoint epistemology involves three propositions:

(1) Knowledge is socially situated. (2) Marginalized groups are socially situated in ways that make it more possible for them to be aware of things and ask questions than it is for the non-marginalized. (3) Research, particularly that focused on power relations, should begin with the lives of the marginalized. 

He begins with a simple thought experiment: suppose that one half of a caste system works each day on the factory floor, the other half in the offices, and nobody ever switches.  An empiricist would, he points out, approach the first group, if knowledge about factory floors is sought (and the second if knowledge of the workings of office buildings is sought).  Accordingly, in such a world there is “a clear sense in which knowledge would be socially situated”.  
After adding the assumption that factory workers are worse off than the office workers, so that they constitute a marginalized group, Kofi Bright concludes:

What is more, for at least some things… the marginalised are clearly in a better position to know what's going on and ask pertinent questions, for just the same reason as above.

What is unclear is why there is “more”.  What exactly does marginalization add, epistemically?  Kofi Bright has thus far argued that factory workers know more than office workers about how factories operate simply on account of their social situation, which as an empiricist must mean because the experiences provided by their work in factories are not available to the office workers.  That’s proposition (1).  But how does adding the assumption that factory workers are worse off lead to (2), especially when the conclusion is based on “just the same reason as above”?  How does the fact that one position is better than the other at gaining knowledge of factory work, because it involves factory work, lead to the conclusion that marginalization is a further epistemic advantage?
This part of the argument is based on the premise that the marginalized caste has more to be concerned about, such as “the orders telegraphed in from the office blocks, which they have every reason to pay attention to lest the food rations cease”.  The idea is that if one must worry about orders from the office blocks, on pain of starvation, then this will keep one sharper and more focused on the relationship between the castes in comparison to those who are not subject to such pressure.  
Let me note, to begin, that the suggestion that fear causes the mind to sharpen and focus, rather than dull and blur, is not a tenet of empiricism but is in fact an empirical proposition concerning human psychology.  It may very well be true, of course, but it does not follow from empiricism (which is an a priori philosophical theory), so if the empiricist believes it, s/he ought to base that belief on the empirical evidence in its favour.  Accordingly, it is this evidence that has to be taken to favour (2), not (1) nor empiricism itself, which as a philosophical commitment must remain neutral on this question, at least so far as it offers up a priori arguments. 
In fact, this point cuts a bit more deeply.  For, in order to comply with (1), empiricist standpoint theory must insist that it is the social psychologists, not empiricist philosophers, who are best placed to know of the relationship between social conditions, such as oppression, and psychological states such as belief (I assume beliefs are necessary for knowledge).  Moreover, the typical empiricist would agree, I suppose, that these psychologists must do more than haphazardly observe factory-office interaction, and then draw whatever conclusions occur to them off the top of their heads.  Rather, they need to engage in the proper selection and collection of data followed by appropriate scientific analysis, such as statistical tests, comparison against established theories, etc.; in short, reasoning their way toward a conclusion.  So, it is not simple observation of factory-office relationships, but the proper application of scientific methodologies to properly attuned observation, that leads to knowledge of the power relations in play.  After all, psychologists can make mistakes and occasionally have to retract or modify their conclusions (which is just to say that proper reasoning is required).  Accordingly, social situatedness does not lead  straight to knowledge.  What is required is the proper gathering of evidence combined with good empirical analysis.  So, as a matter of a priori philosophical argument, the question of the relationship between a particular social situation, such as ‘factory worker’, and a particular knowledge claim remains open.  
The only way to resist this conclusion is to insist that the epistemic advantage enjoyed by the social psychologists (who properly apply the scientific tools that allow for correct inferences from properly collected data) just is their social position; so it really is social position that holds knowledge even in this case.  This, however, is simply to beg the question because it builds epistemic mastery into the definition of a social position.  In other words, what makes knowledge reside in a social position here is the fact that a particular social group has better epistemic tools than its competitors.  But even a rationalist foundationalist can agree that S is epistemically privileged if and only if S is epistemically better than its rivals: this is trivial.  So, empiricism implies standpoint theory either on the basis of synthetic a priori claims, or else by trivializing it.
A part of Kofi Bright’s argument refers to incentives:

…if you had limited time and resources to interview people and find out about race relations in some town in 1947 Alabama, which group do you think [you] should spend more time getting to know, should you want to include in the research team… I take it that an empiricist, somebody who thinks that knowledge tracks degree of experience and incentive to really think things through, is going to want to favour the marginalised group here.

What is important to note here is that this implies that it is not the mere existence of incentives that epistemically advantages a social group but, instead, the fact that the incentives lead the members of the group to reason better, to “think things through”.  However, the incentive to think better does not always lead to better thinking.  A highly motivated lover of physics, who wants desperately to prove his intellectual worth, may enter a Ph.D. program, work hard, and nevertheless graduate with less knowledge of physics than his disengaged, wealthy classmate who has no real interest in physics but wants to pass the time until her trust fund matures and who happens to be a mathematical prodigy who easily masters physics at the highest levels.  
In general, incentive is a necessary condition for achievement, not a sufficient condition.  After all, who has more incentive to redress persistent economic inequality in western societies than the marginalized?  That incentive has not led to increased equality over the past fifty years.  In fact, inequality has worsened over that time.  The fact is that marginalized people need more than incentive to fight inequality; they need the means to do so.  The powerful are happy with our current distribution of wealth, so they ensure that roadblocks to change exist.  Overcoming roadblocks requires more than incentive and, of course, the world is filled with roadblocks on the path to knowledge.
            So, it is not mere incentive that provides someone with epistemic advantage but, rather, the combination of the incentive with the skill and opportunity to both learn more than others and to succeed in doing so.  What this means is that before we can determine whether social position is epistemically relevant, and if so how, we need to know which tools best serve in gaining knowledge and how they should be applied.  In other words, we need to determine the proper standards of evidence and reasoning before we can assess the epistemic status of a social group.  But this is just to say that standpoint theory is false.  So I disagree with Kofi Bright when he asserts that empiricism’s implication of standpoint theory is obvious, “really quite a banal point”.  I think, on the contrary, that empiricism is incompatible with standpoint theory.
            Let me conclude with an example.  To this day, here are those who study and immerse themselves in astrological writing, theory, and practice and who take themselves to have a great deal of knowledge concerning the relationship between celestial bodies and human affairs as a result.  I disagree on the grounds that astrology is a false theory, based on Aristotelian teleology, which has no role in contemporary astronomy.  What the demographic category ‘astrologer’ amounts to, or what demographic groups astrologers occupy, is simply irrelevant; what I care about is whether they are applying correct physical models properly.  It is the thinking, not the social position, that matters.

Monday 13 April 2020

Subjectivist Truth

These thoughts are inspired by Liam Kofi Bright’s blog post on subjectivism about truth (see here).  In the post he insists that we distinguish subjectivism from relativism.  The latter is the doctrine that what is true for one may not be true for another, so that each thinker offers a distinct perspective or reference frame against which truth is determined.  The problem with this view, he argues, is that it presupposes an objective conception that can survey all viewpoints at once and assert that each has its own extension for the truth predicate.  Resisting this, the subjectivist insists that truth is exhausted by his or her own viewpoint: what is true for him/her is what is true, period.  There are no other viewpoints to consider according to subjectivism.

 

Kofi Bright insists that subjectivism does not fall prey to the objection that the subjectivist cannot make sense of error because the subjectivist can accept that: (1) others believe things that he/she disagrees with, so those others can be wrong; and (2) the subjectivist him/herself has believed things in the past that he/she no longer believes, in which case the subjectivist can make sense of having been wrong.  What the subjectivist cannot make sense is simply being wrong in his/her beliefs right now but this is not a problem, according to Kofi Bright, because “that is just to say: they are self-consistent”.

 

Okay, so if this is right, then one core idea of subjectivism is:

 

            (S1)      Right now, all of my beliefs are true.

  

But how could the subjectivist combine this with something else that Kofi Bright insists they can admit, namely:

 

            (S2)      In the past, I have believed falsely?

 

Presumably, (S1) applies to any time one wishes to consider: at the time, the subjectivist has no false beliefs.  On the other hand, some past times include the subjectivist believing falsely.  So, according to (S1), the subjectivist has no false beliefs right now.  According to (S2), tomorrow it could be the case that the subjectivist had a false belief that day before, i.e. right now.  The only way this could be the case is if something that is truly believed today can properly be false tomorrow.  

 

Now, it is perfectly commonplace to revise one’s past beliefs, of course, but normally this results in the judgement that what one believed in the past was false at the time; one just didn’t realize it.  In this case, however, it seems that the subjectivist cannot rightly claim that what s/he believed in the past was false without admitting that there was a time at which she had a false belief, in which case (S1) can only be said to apply to one time, whichever time is present.  In short, the subjectivist must belief that her/his beliefs right now cannot contain falsehood, but that this same does not apply to any times other than the present.  

 

What this suggests is that subjectivism is also a kind of presentism, according to which only the present is real, so one cannot generalize or quantify over non-present times.  ‘For all times, t: P’ can only mean something like ‘From the perspective of right now, for all times, t: P’, which does seem in accordance with subjectivism.  However, this isn’t without difficulty.  First, it requires an answer to the various objections against presentism, which is no easy feat.  Secondly, it renders subjectivism hard to motivate, for consider that if it is possible for the subjectivist to be wrong at any past time, on what basis can s/he believe that the current time must be an exception?  Presumably, on the presentist basis that only the present is real at all, but then that robs the view of any substantive sense in which the subjectivist was wrong: a past mistake is not a real mistake because the past is not real.  Unreal mistakes are not mistakes, it would seem.  So it is hard to see how to combine (S1) and (S2).

 

A different kind of worry for the subjectivist is considered by Kofi Bright, and that is the idea that we can simply make things true by believing them, and this is a problem because the mind just doesn’t seem to have that kind of ontological power.  He insists that the subjectivist may very well have a number of causal beliefs that rule out this kind of power.  Nevertheless, if the sincere belief that P suffices for the truth of P, then there is some potentially troubling connection between the two here.  Kofi Bright replies that the subjectivist can distinguish between constitution and causation and 

 

insist that while they think a belief's being true is constituted by their believing it they are not saying their belief causes it to be true, nor that its being true causes the state of affairs it describes to obtain.

 

So let us consider the idea that what it is for a belief to be true is for me, the subjectivist, to believe it, without attributing causal power here.  Whatever constitution amounts to, it will entail a biconditional:

 

            (S3)      It is true that P iff I believe that P.

 

I think that (S3) causes trouble for subjectivism in that it will commit the subjectivist to some strong and dubious propositions.

 

To see this, consider that if the subjectivist is to have anything like the worldview of contemporary natural science among her/his beliefs, then s/he will believe that we are biological creatures who evolved through time under selection pressure; at the very least, that we are physical entities, at least in part, who were created by physical, chemical, and biological processes.  So, let’s call this the first premise:

 

            (P1)     We are evolved or at least created biological creatures.

 

Secondly, since truth is constituted by belief, the subjectivist must believe that she is capable of holding beliefs:

 

            (P2)     I, the subjectivist, am capable of holding beliefs.

 

Thirdly, since, within her/his subjective belief-set, we assume, with Kofi-Bright, that something close to the modern scientific worldview exists, we assume that s/he agrees that reality contains some kinds that cannot form beliefs (rocks, soil, water, stars, etc.), so:

 

            (P3)     The world contains entities that are not capable of holding beliefs

 

In other words:

 

            (P3*)   Not everything is capable of forming beliefs.

 

Fourthly, let us assume that the difference between that which is capable of belief and that which is not is accounted for buy some difference in the nature of the kid under consideration, so that  if one is capable of forming beliefs, then one has a capacity that other things lack:

 

            (P4)      Belief-forming kinds have a capacity that other kinds lack.

 

Fifthly, believing anything depends on the existence of the capacity to form beliefs.  Without this capacity, there would be no beliefs.  Put another way, that a belief exists entails that the capacity to form beliefs exists.  So:

 

            (P5)     The existence of a belief depends on the capacity to form beliefs.

 

Sixthly, therefore:

 

            (P6)     If I believe that P, then I have the capacity to form the belief that P.

 

Let us return, now, to (S3), and substitute:

 

            (B1)     It is true that (I have the capacity to believe) iff I believe that (I have the capacity to believe).

 

Let us assume that we can use the T-schema:

 

(T)        It is true that P iff P

 

on the left hand side of (B1) to obtain:

 

            (B2)     I have the capacity to believe iff I believe that (I have the capacity to believe)

 

I will follow Kofi Bright and insist that this is not to attribute some strange causal power to the mind.  It is not that my belief that I have the capacity to believe reaches out into the causal realm and creates my psychological structure but that, somehow, having that structure is constituted by having the belief that I have that structure:

 

            (S4)      That I have the capacity to believe is constituted by my belief that I have the capacity to believe.

 

Even this, however, seems wrong for it would entail that having the capacity to believe depends on the existence of a belief, but a belief cannot exist without the capacity, so the dependence runs the other way around.  The capacity has logical and explanatory (if not causal) priority.  To allow the existence of belief-forming capacity to be constituted by the existence of a belief is to conjure up something out of nothing: the belief exist which explains the existence of the capacity to believe, which makes no sense.

 

There are, of course, many places a subjectivist may try to block the argument, but none of them is particularly appealing:

 

1.     S/He can reject the idea that we are biological creatures, products of our environment

2.     S/He can insist that beliefs exist without the capacity to form beliefs

3.     S/He can insist that even if A constitutes B, B can still have logical or explanatory priority over A.

4.     S/He can reject whatever logic underlies moves such as those from (P5) to (P6)

5.     S/He can insist that, as subjectivist, the subject cannot be expected to be subject to the same explanatory standards or requirements of anything else: we are sui generis.

 

In a sense, (1) and (5) amount to the same: the subjectivist, as a believer, is unlike or outside of the rest of nature, and indeed this can be seen even more clearly by substituting the proposition that I exist in (S3):

 

            (S5)      That I exist is constituted by my belief that I exist.

 

Here is the image of a belief conjuring the existence of the believer, not causally of course, but still: the dependence here is the wrong way around.  

 

On the other hand, (2) would suggest that beliefs are not to be viewed as dependent on the believer: they are free-standing states, independent of a cognitive structure.  So, rocks, soil, and stars might form beliefs after all.  

 

With regard to (3) whatever constitution is, it must surely be a relation of some kind of priority such that the properties of the constituted kind depend on the constituting matter.  If not, then it is hard to see what constitution could amount to, but I am willing to entertain suggestions.

 



Finally, there is no easy way to sum up how to respond to (4) because there are many non-standard logical systems, many of which may have much to be said in their favour.  Still, I think it is safe to say that this shows that the subjectivist takes on some very strong commitments.  After all, moves like that from (P5) to (P6) are simply applications of rules like universal instantiation, and if we must reject those to accept subjectivism, then subjectivism must have a very compelling defence, for otherwise we must simply ask: why not just reject subjectivism instead?

 

Thursday 26 March 2020

Mind-Independence and Value

Over at The Electric Agora, Daniel Kaufman posted an interesting essay on morality and objectivity (here), which carries on a debate he has been engaged in with Spencer Case.  I left the argument below in the comments there, but thought I would repost it here as it does constitute something that I take to be an implication of views I hold elsewhere.
Here is an argument for a kind of realism about moral values (in what follows 'Real' with a capital-R means 'mind-independent').
First premise: realms of what you call the objective but non-Real have the following property: the rules, norms, and facts involved are what they are in virtue of acts of human deliberation and decision. There are publicly accessible facts concerning the rules of tennis, for example, but they are subject to revision by us: should a governing body, or sufficient numbers of people, decide that there are new rules, then there are new rules. 
Second: in order for there to be realms whose rules/norms/facts are determined, at least in part, by human deliberation and decision, then human beings must be the kind of creatures who can deliberate, and that requires that we have a certain kind of structure, for the truly structureless cannot give rise to anything, let alone deliberation. The nature of this structure cannot be determined by acts of deliberation, for the latter depend on that structure for their existence. 
Conclusion: there is structure to human beings that is Real, i.e. mind-independent. Let us assume for now that this structure is biological.
Here is a neo-Aristotelian take on all this. It is plausible to suppose that biological structure leads to objective facts about human beings, and so can determine, for many aspects of being a human, that there are some conditions or states (the virtues) that lead to flourishing and some (the vices) that diminish flourishing: some things promote health, for example, whether we like it or not (eat your vegetables). So, in reasoning about moral matters, i.e. how to live best as a human being, the realm of the Real will be a factor – not necessarily the only factor, but one nonetheless. Hence, we can conclude that moral reasoning must be at least partly Realistic.
This seems rather persuasive to me. All the same, I in fact lean toward subjectivism when it comes to most of what is contained in actually existing moral codes, which generally strike me as the attempted universalization of local, contingent, and historically conditioned preference-sets. People who argue about morality often seem to think that their own success can be attributed to the specifics of their moral or cultural or social code – which are, therefore, projected outwards – but it seems more likely that, since most systems include some people who flourish, it is something that is common to all systems that grounds well-being, and that is what contributes to flourishing given our nature. Put another way, most moral argumentation seems to be conducted without considering human nature, and so is like arguing over Einstein’s Field Equations without considering physics or math. 
So I guess I would say that I lean toward *theoretical* Realism about values but, in most cases, *practical* subjectivism. This is, admittedly, a strange position (though perhaps something not too far from Plato).
Anyway, if you have any interest in formulating a response I would be interested in it, but I found your essay interesting and though-provoking regardless.

Wednesday 18 March 2020

Special Relativity, Entropy, and the Direction of Time



Assuming that, as far as perception and experience are concerned, space is a three-dimensional, and time a one-dimensional, projection of a four-dimensional space-time, the following question arises: why does the brain, a material organ, break down a four-dimensional, relativistic space-time into three spatial dimensions and one temporal dimension? There is really only one answer that suggests itself, and it is that as biological products of natural selection our survival depends on tracking entropy: we need to find pockets of low entropy in order to discover sources of work that we may employ in order to maintain our own relatively low entropy, and since the entropic gradient is aligned along the temporal dimension, it is to our benefit to evolve to single out that dimension from the other three in order to focus on it and thereby be able to track entropy. That is, it is important to our survival that we find low entropy systems in order to secure energy.

This seems straightforward enough but it does, however, raise a deeper question: why is entropy organized along the temporal dimension alone; why not along another dimension, or two or more dimensions? Why did evolution find it necessary to endow us with perceptual and cognitive faculties that see the world as a three-dimensional array of material and objects that are evolving in a fourth dimension rather than some other way?

We know that in Minkowski space-time, neither spatial distances nor temporal durations have geometric significance on their own: only their combination in terms of Einstein’s Interval Formula:

     I2 = dt2 – ds2

has physical significance. What this entails is that there is no preferred set of spatial axes for the universe, no sense in which one can be right or wrong in labelling one direction “east” rather than “north” or “up” rather than “sideways”, and so on. All such spatial directions are significant only in relation to an observer; the universe itself doesn’t single out a particular direction in space.

Accordingly, if entropy increase were to be correlated with a spatial axis, it would be impossible for evolution to track it because it is impossible for physically real correlations to exist in relation to one or more spatial axes. The pattern of entropic increase would simply disappear from all spatial perspectives except one, i.e. from those corresponding to the rotation of the particular choice of axes. If a pattern is deeply dependent on a directional convention in this way, then there is no way for the non-directed, probabilistic processes of evolution to latch onto it, for there is, in reality, no probabilistic pattern to be detected: the pattern would be an observer effect, just like some works of art are constructed so that only when looked at directly is an image visible; all other angles show no discernible pattern - there is no pattern inherent to the image itself in such a case. In essence, if entropy were to be aligned with one or more spatial axes, the pattern of the second law of thermodynamics would simply disappear with movement in space, rendering impossible to have both freedom of movement and the ability to track entropy.

Given the non-directionality of space, entropy increase could not be aligned along any spatial dimension, so there could be no fitness relevant pressure to track any such gradient spatially. The only remaining option is that what we evolved to detect, namely the entropy gradient, is aligned with the fourth, temporal, dimension. But how could this be the case? According to (I), temporal duration frame-dependent – how much time there is between any two events will vary, though in such a way as to preserve the interval, I, between them. Moreover, the direction of time does not make an appearance in (I) since whether we put a positive or negative sign in front of the (frame-dependent) measure of time will make no difference to the interval because the value for time is squared in (I). This is one of the senses in which it is thought that Relativity counts against the common-sense notion that time passes from past to future.

If we leave things here, however, then we are faced with a problem: we know that entropy is coordinated with the temporal dimension, but if that dimension lacks an inherent direction, then there is no reason for entropy to uniformly increase or decrease along it: any such pattern would only be apparent, like a spatially oriented second law of thermodynamics, that exists only from some points of view. So if there is a genuine entropy gradient along the temporal dimension, which would account for our having evolved to single out time from space, then we must conclude that as a matter of fact, if not mathematical necessity, the fourth, temporal of the universe is inherently directed or asymmetric.

However, precisely because the temporal duration is squared in (I), it makes no difference to the mathematics of the interval to suppose that there is an objective, physically significant direction to time. In other words, even if there is a real difference between +t and -t, the interval will wash that out by squaring the value. So, the mathematics of Special Relativity is not impacted by the assumption that time is directed in the following sense: at each four-dimensional space-time point, a unique direction is defined, from the past light cone to the future. We can think of it as an array of vectors originating at the point and directed toward each point on the interior of one half of the light cone only; alternatively, we can state that between any two time-like separated space-time points, there exists a vector that defines the past-future orientation. This way, local temporal asymmetry is relativistically invariant and from the frame of reference of the surface of the Earth, there is a genuine pattern for the non-directed mechanisms of evolution to stumble upon and register for future iterations of variation-selection-inheritance.

In other words, the very fact that the four-dimensional, invariant Interval is broken down by the brain into a three-plus-one dimensional cognitive-perceptual model provides excellent reason to believe that the direction of time is not an illusion but, rather, a relativistic invariant.

Why does this matter? Well, it matters because there is a strong current of argumentation in the philosophy of time/physics to the effect that both the passage and direction of time are illusory, mere mental projections onto a fully symmetric underlying physical reality. If the foregoing argument is correct, then this is unlikely to be true simply because it would be unable to account for the fact that evolution reached a wide-spread and relatively stable equilibrium in constructing human beings to experience and understand the world as 3+1-dimensional rather than 4+0-, 2+2, or 1+3-dimensional. More fundamentally, it cannot account for the fact that entropy is aligned with any of the dimensions in (I) at all: if there is no fact of the matter as to which direction in space-time is locally future-oriented, there would be no entropic gradient in the first place for evolution to eventually track. In other words, without an objective temporal direction, there could be no entropic gradient at all since from one temporal perspective the universe would consist of mostly improbable transitions and that perspective would have to be considered equally valid compared to the opposite perspective in which probable transitions are the rule. But any viewpoint according to which a highly probable and highly improbable set of transitions need to be considered equally valid must surely be incorrect.

So, it seems that the best way to view the implications of Relativity Theory for the debate over the nature of time is that it combines with the theory of evolution to suggest that Einstein-Minkowski space-time includes a temporally oriented vector field defined at every space-time point that determines the future light cone from that point. The vectors themselves are perhaps to be viewed as unit vectors with frame-dependent lengths determined by the time-dilation implied by Lorenz Transformations.

The upshot for the philosophy of time is that a naturalistic picture of time that combines Einstein-Minkowski space-time with Darwinian evolution is not only compatible with asymmetric, i.e. directed, time but in fact demands it. In short, the direction of time is not an illusion. Furthermore, so long as we can define temporal passage in terms of directed temporal ordering, then this view is compatible with objective temporal passage as well. Since, as I’ve argued elsewhere, there is no problem with a deflationary, relational conception of temporal passage, we can conclude that the Theory of Relativity is no threat to the idea that time genuinely passes from the past toward the future.

Wednesday 22 January 2020

Understanding as an Alethic Concept

One of the ways in which I have defended the value of the humanities is by reference to understanding, as in “the humanities help to improve our understanding of ourselves and our environment, and this is important”.   This is both initially plausible and helps to lay out a kind of value that is distinct from the gathering of knowledge, which the sciences seem to do better than the humanities. 

 

One advantage of taking this route is that “understanding” is a rather wide-ranging term that has many meanings, so people can import various, positive, interpretations into the phrase “improve our understanding”.  This is, of course, also a disadvantage, for it renders the basic defence ambiguous.  So what does it mean to say that the humanities improve our understanding?

 

Among the rather familiar and straightforward meanings of “understanding” we could list:

 

·      The knowledge of linguistic meaning: e.g. “x understands English”

·      A sympathetic or gentle approach or demeanour: “x was very understanding of y’s situation”

·      An informal agreement: “x and y came to an understanding”

·      A belief state that is the result of inference or observation: “I understand that you have changed jobs”

·      An assumption, perhaps unspoken or hidden: “it is understood that everyone will speak respectfully at department meetings”

·      A cognitive ability: “it is impossible for non-human animals to understand that moral obligations exist.”

 

When it comes to the value that humanities offer, I think, however, that the best meaning is something along these lines:

 

·      To understand something, P, is to realize or learn the significance of P; e.g. “I understand that this is a very complex issue that impacts x, y, and, z and will require further investigation”

 

That seems to capture what the humanities are after: to discover and impart methods, tools, writings, interpretations, and arguments that will allow us to learn something of significance about something, which may be that that something is in fact significant.  So, understanding, will result when some argument or analysis makes clear to us: (1) that P is significant/important; or (2) what is significant/important about P.

 

This indicates that understanding is similar in certain respects to explanation.  An explanation, E, of P makes P clear to us or, as I would say, enables us to see why or that P is true, either by entailing P, rendering P probable, or fitting P coherently into our prior body of knowledge.  

In the case of explanation, however, E can explain P even if E is false.  For example, Aristotle explained why material bodies sink in water by appeal to (1) hylomorphism, which includes the claim that bodies (“substances”) include an immanent form; (2) a theory of space that is structured formally, with “earth” at the center, surrounded by, in order, “water”, “air”, and “fire”; and (3) a principle which states that anything with form F will naturally seek space that is F.  Given (1) – (3) it follows that rocks, “earth”, will sink because the “earth” form of space is below the “water” part.  So, (1) – (3) are explanatory.

 

They are not, however, true.  Accordingly, I suggest, Aristotle’s explanation cannot provide us with any understanding of the motions of bodies. In particular, it cannot offer any additional understanding than what was contained in the prior observation that rocks fall in water, fire rises in air, and so on.  Aristotle’s attempt to move from those straightforward observations to a systematic elucidation of what is going on when bodies move ultimately fails for the simple reason that it is, so we currently believe, false: we no longer accept his account of the structure of space and reject his formal account of attraction (bodies don’t naturally move, we think, but instead naturally continue in their current state).  So even though Aristotelian physics neatly explains motion in virtue of providing a set of propositions that entails a great deal of what we observe, it does not offer understanding of motion.  This is, of course, not unique: it is straightforward to construct a set of propositions that are false but entail or make probable some other proposition that is known to be true.

 

Let’s consider a made-up case in which x is afraid of the dark and posits that this was caused by x’s abduction by extraterrestrials one night years ago, which left a deep-seated fear that is brought to the surface in the dark.  This would explain the fear: the proposition that x was abducted combined with the proposition that this was traumatic and that trauma can leave a lasting fear that is associated with the time of day during which the initial event occurred, entails or renders probable a current fear.  However, x does not in fact understand why the fear exists, if the abduction never occurred.  Further, a non-occurrent event cannot increase x’s awareness of the significance or importance of the fear: the abduction proposition adds nothing on that score either (no more than supposing x’s fear is caused by unicorns or magic).

 

What this suggests is that the understanding sought by the humanities is in fact an alethic concept: whatever it is that increases understanding must be true.  The same applies for a good explanation, so understanding is something like a good or correct explanation of the significance of something.

 

If this is right, then it immediately raises a question: how can the humanities improve our understanding if they do not either: (1) discover the truth, at least in part; or (2) apply truth-preserving methods to previously discovered truths?  In the absence of truth, there can be no understanding, so the humanities must either be able to determine the truth or else take the truth and derive something from it that clarifies the importance of something.  

 

In the latter case, this process of derivation must be truth preserving or probability/coherence increasing; otherwise it will not in fact increase our understanding.  It may of course be possible to do something in addition to determining the truth or an alethic consequence from what is known.  That is, the process of increasing understanding may involve deriving something, P, from something known as well as situating this truth in some kind of context that is enlightening.  But again, if this context is not factual, situating a truth in it cannot improve our understanding, so there is a kind of alethic constraint at all stages of the process.

 

So, if all this is roughly along the right lines, then any humanities project aimed at improving understanding must, at least in part, either discover the truth or else work with the truth to derive further truths that are significant or can be contextualized with other truths in such a way as to produce an improvement in our awareness of the significance or importance of something, which must also be of genuine or true significance, for otherwise we have no understanding (if something isn’t truly significant, then we cannot really understand its significance.)  

 

In short, if we want to improve our understanding of P, then:

 

1.     P must be true

2.     The theory (story/account/proposition/…), T, that improves the understanding of P must be true

3.     T must have some truth preserving or probability raising relation to P (otherwise it cannot help us see that/why P is true)

4.     T may also do more than (3): for example it ay relate P to a context, C, or another understood proposition, Q.

5.     If (4), then C or Q must be true as well.

 

I don’t, in other words, see how the appeal to “understanding”, in the defence of the value of the anything, gets a discipline off the hook of either being truth-producing or at least truth-preserving.  So, any field that aims at understanding must employ methods that have one or both of these properties.  This, of course, includes the humanities.

 

One worry about (1) – (5) above is whether it is compatible with a robust notion of fictional truth, i.e. one in which fictional propositions can be literally and directly true, as in “that Centaurs have four legs is true” instead of “that Geek myth-makers said that Centaurs have four legs is true”.  If one takes it to be true that Centaurs have four legs, then presumably we could offer a study to increase our understanding of Centaurs themselves, which seem never to have existed, rather than our understanding of their story-tellers, which do or did exist.  This seems awkward.  I am not sure how much of a problem any of this is, but it seems to me to have a rather felicitous implication: there is reason to adopt an indirect account of fictional truth in which propositions about fictional entities are in fact about the acts and thoughts of writers and story-tellers, in which case the study of mythology can aid in our understanding insofar as it aids in our understanding of human beings who make up tales and the societies and times in which they live.  This seems perfectly respectable, so long as it is alethic in the ways mentioned above.