This is a follow up to
the previous post that cast a skeptical eye on the ability of the humanities to
produce knowledge or meaningful understanding.
I want to comment here on the possibility of constructing a humanities based “theory” to
elucidate the world, ourselves, or the relation between the two.
To see deeper into the
problem with the assumption that something such as a theory emanating from a
humanities discipline can reliably provide information about the world –
including the mind of an author – I will consider the description of one such
theory, Derrida’s deconstructionism, as provided in the Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy (SEP).
What is deconstruction according to this article? One of Derrida’s earliest answers is
described as follows:
Simply,
deconstruction is a criticism of Platonism, which is defined by the belief that
existence is structured in terms of oppositions (separate substances or forms)
and that the oppositions are hierarchical, with one side of the opposition
being more valuable than the other. The first phase of
deconstruction attacks this belief by reversing the
Platonistic hierarchies.
Supposing that Plato’s
alleged hierarchies are mistaken, it is unclear what value there is in
reversing them. The reversal of a false hierarchy
isn’t necessarily a true one. For
example, if we reverse the false hierarchy, men are superior to women,
we get the equally false, women are superior to men. Moreover, if Plato himself is guilty of some
form of complex fiction writing, i.e. failing to engage in anything other than
his own abstractions that lack grounding in reality, then reversing them is to
similarly play in the realm of fiction, much like analyzing Tolkien’s works for
hierarchies among Orcs, and then reversing them; what could that possibly teach
us? Perhaps it could teach us something
about the opinions of the author of the reversal, but without both more context
and a relatively sophisticated psychological theory applicable to the author,
it is not easy to say what would be learned here.
The SEP entry
continues:
On
the basis of the reversal… we can see that something like a decision (a perhaps
impossible decision) must have been made at the beginning of the metaphysical
tradition, a decision that instituted the hierarchy…
This is
plausible. Decisions – assumptions,
presuppositions, etc. – as to the rules and axioms of investigation must be
made prior to any inquiry. It does not
follow, however, that such decisions are arbitrary, unfounded, unjustified, or
not conducive to discovering the truth.
They may be just the right decisions required to uncover the structure
of reality, and the reasoning they initiate may be logically sound. What this means is that there is no reason to
believe that the mere act of reversing the result of such decisions will lead
to a better account of reality.
Now let us turn to the
second phase of deconstruction:
The
previously inferior term must be re-inscribed as the “origin”
or “resource” of the opposition and hierarchy itself.
There are a couple of
problems here. First, as just noted, because
the need to rely on “decisions” – axioms, rules, etc. – in order to get inquiry
off the ground does not entail that the decisions are bad or conducive
to falsehood, it follows that we cannot assume that any hierarchy that results
is necessarily wrong. Hence, to elevate
what Plato saw as the less valuable of two parts of a hierarchy – say matter over
form – is not necessarily to do anything important or revealing. Nor does it follow that the inferior term
must have some fundamental or central role in the creation of the hierarchy. Perhaps Plato elevated form over matter
because he was in fact obsessed with the material – maybe he feared the
physical body – and felt some paradoxical need to overwhelm it – put it in its
place – in his theory; but perhaps not.
The mere fact that there is a decision here tells us nothing, because similar
decisions are required for any inquiry, including Derrida’s.
In general, from the fact that a hierarchy is incorrect, it doesn’t follow that the previously inferior term is the origin of the hierarchy itself. Consider:
Non-human animals are more intelligent than humans.
This is, apparently at least, the wrong way around, so we must reverse the hierarchy:
Humans are more intelligent than non-human animals.
It does not follow that re-inscribing “non-human animal” as the “origin” of this opposition and hierarchy is correct, or even makes any sense. On the contrary, it appears that if anything it is a preference for, or bias toward, the human that is the origin here. At any rate, it is the relation between the two that is the cause of the hierarchy, not any one on its own, so to propose a theory of reversal and inversion on a priori grounds is simply suspect.
Secondly, unless we
assume that Plato himself discovered something deep and true about the essence
of reality in his hierarchical oppositions, he just messed up the order, any
act of inversion will tell us nothing. So…
how do we know that Plato was right here?
Suppose someone divides the world into red things and geometric objects,
making the latter more important than the former. This clearly seems to be a hierarchy that
tells us nothing about reality, so inverting it so that the red things are more
important will similarly tell us nothing.
Well, perhaps I am not
properly considering the nature of this re-inscription, so:
How
would this re-inscription or redefinition of appearance work? Here we would
have to return to the idea that every appearance or every experience is temporal.
In the experience of the present, there is always a small difference between
the moment of now-ness and the past and the future… this infinitesimal difference is not only a
difference that is non-dualistic, but also it is a difference that is, as
Derrida would say, “undecidable.” Although the minuscule difference is
virtually unnoticeable in everyday common experience, when we in fact notice
it, we cannot decide if we are experiencing a memory or a
present perception, if we are experiencing a present perception or an
anticipation… Insofar as the difference is undecidable…[it] destabilizes the
original decision that instituted the hierarchy.
There is certainly work
in the experience of time that suggests that any particular experience is a
structured mix that combines perception of what is occurring at that time with memory
and anticipation (see, e.g., Horwich 1987) – experience has content that is
temporally structured to include a past, present, and future component. What is not clear, is whether there is
no way to distinguish these at all; even fuzzy boundaries can be boundaries,
and who knows what cognitive science might discover. Moreover, it is unclear why this
undecidability would invalidate Platonic arguments about, say, the form of the
good, or the nature of mathematical knowledge.
There may be an argument for this, but since Platonic metaphysics is the
result of a long period of contemplation and analysis, there is no obvious move
from a feature of momentary perceptions to the results of long, thorough
contemplation.
When reflecting upon
the nature of number or goodness, one may be doing little more than staring out
of a window, pen and notebook in hand, mulling over arguments of Frege and Russell,
or Kant and Aristotle. The perception of
the trees and birds beyond the pane of glass may – though may not – be an
essentially entangled mix of what is seen then with memory and
anticipation. It is not at all clear,
however, what impact this has on one’s reflection of Frege’s attempts to
translate the Peano axioms into axioms of the predicate calculus. Suppose, as one read The Foundations of
Arithmetic, one’s perceptions were consistently temporally mixed in just
this way: what is the significance of this fact for reflecting on whether the
logical reduction of arithmetic is sound?
It would seem that the inability to separate the temporal components of experience
would have no bearing on this. Further, even
if one cannot separate out the components of experience at the time they are
happening, it doesn’t follow that one can’t look back on one’s experience with
the benefit of additional information and then disentangle the strands, which
might lead to a principled way to do so in general. In short, it is not at all clear how the
alleged features of temporal experience would undermine the choice of axioms
and rules of inquiry that are required to get any investigation off the ground. Conversely, if such features do destabilize
all such choices, then they would undermine the principles that undergird the
deconstructionist inversion.
So this is an example
of a theory applied to a text that is supposed to result in something
interesting and informative about reality.
However, if the text itself is simply off base, then the move proposed
by this theory will not likely tell us anything interesting or informative; at
least it gives us no reason to suppose so because it offers no means of correcting
the text other than rearranging its parts, which is of not help if the text is
fundamentally incomplete. Moreover, we have
to have some reason to believe that the inversion proposed by the theory is a
good move: likely to be informative, corrective, truth-conducive, or what have
you. For this, more than a priori
reflection on texts is required, because what we want to know is when texts are
better or worse at getting things right.
Inverted Plato vs. Regular Plato leaves us in no position to judge. It is like being told that A believes that P
and B believes that not-P. Without evidence
from outside their belief states, we have no way of adjudicating between them.
So, until we can
demonstrate that humanistic writing, that isn’t grounded in math and science,
can reveal something about reality, then any attempt to reverse, pervert,
subvert, or otherwise undermine previous such writing cannot be said to amount
to knowledge of anything. What, then,
can it tell us? I am not sure. Perhaps something about the mind of Derrida,
but I am not sure what that would be without more empirical evidence about him
and how human minds work in general; i.e. not without some science.
Obviously more has to
be said to make the case. In particular,
I am, here, relying on a single source about a single aspect of a single author’s
work, so it would be illegitimate to generalize from this single case. It is, however, illustrative of the point I
made in the previous post: that a non-scientific theory of texts applied to
texts to create other texts does not seem to be the kind of thing that will generate
knowledge of the world; at best it would generate knowledge of the applier of
the theory, but even that would be suspect without detailed empirical
investigation. So, the question is what
the theory – in this case a principled inversion – could possibly teach us
about the world.
Let me end with a
limited defence of Plato. It seems to me
that his “elevation” of forms had to do primarily with an observation, that
Euclidean geometry, which is an a priori and formal axiomatic system,
manages to correctly describe space. He
proposed, along Pythagorean lines, that the explanation of this is that reality
itself is ultimately mathematical in nature, so that it shares its form with
the Euclidean axioms. If this is
correct, then the basic structure of reality is timeless and unchanging, in
which case the idea that the world is a place of change and flux must be some
kind of mistake or illusion. This may be
wrong, but it is reflection on the basis of a mathematical-physical knowledge
and observation. So, to return to the original
point, it is far from obvious why a general “inversion” of the resulting system
would be true, interesting, or valuable.
No comments:
Post a Comment