There is a clear sense in which modern science is a
progression away from an anthropocentric worldview toward one in which human
kind and human experience are no longer viewed as central to our understanding
of the general features of the universe.
The scientific revolution ushered in a period of human decentering, which of course continues
to this day.
Aristotelian physics, as sophisticated as it was, revolved
around the human experience of the world.
For example, according to him: the Earth occupies the center of reality
with the far off starts utterly alien to anything we encounter here; just
as we govern ourselves by making decisions about what is best to do, so nature
governs itself in accordance with its proper purposes; just as biological species
seem distinct and categorically different from each other, so they are; and so
on.
If we pick Copernicus as a natural starting point, we can
see the scientific revolution as a rather systematic dismantling of this kind
of perspective. For example: not only is
the Earth not the center of the universe, it isn’t even the center of the solar
system; the universe operates by causal laws devoid of teleological
residue; far from the universe being somehow made for us, we have adapted to it
through eons of variation and selection (and the difference between
species is better understood as one of degree rather than kind); and so on.
Now, one difference between the humanities and the natural
sciences is that while the latter continue to produce a picture of a world that
is largely indifferent to our viewpoint, the humanities remain centered on the
human experience. In studying such human
creations as art, literature, music, sports, and society, the humanities have
as their mission the understanding of the ways in which our endeavours impact ourselves. The sciences
have as their mission the understanding of the impersonal laws that underlie
all phenomena, human or otherwise (this even when studying specifically human
phenomena such as art or communities).
None of this is meant as a complaint against either the
sciences or the humanities. Indeed, I
think it is important and appropriate that we engage in a study of both sides
of the anthropocentric vs. impersonal viewpoint dichotomy.
All of which brings me to philosophy.
Philosophy is a unique discipline in that it has one leg
firmly planted in the spirit of the scientific worldview and the other in the
spirit of the humanistic one. Much of
philosophy is the struggle to understand and, if possible, reconcile this
divide: how can an impersonal universe, as uncovered by scientific inquiry,
contain such things as meaning, consciousness, qualia, morals, counterfactual
truth, mathematical truth, truth at all, and so on?
This is part of what makes philosophy difficult and worthwhile: it is a
bridging discipline that offers insight from a unique vantage point.
All of which brings me to the so-called “core” of
philosophy: metaphysics, epistemology, logic, and the philosophies of language,
mind, and science (I take this usage of "core" from here).
We can, very roughly, divide philosophy into impersonal and
personal, or scientific and humanistic, sides.
Philosophy includes, for example: the attempt to understand both the
structure of causation and also causal talk; the attempt to understand the
nature of time and our experience of time; the nature of moral properties and
the nature of our reactive attitudes; the nature of aesthetic properties as
well as the human experience of art; and so on.
Indeed, without paying attention to both sides of these sorts of
dichotomies, it is hard to imagine the result being anything like philosophy at
all.
All of this is a big part of the reason why philosophy has
to remain in conversation with contemporary science: the psychological and
cognitive sciences will help us to understand the human experience while the
natural sciences help us to understand the world. Without both of these, our philosophizing
will certainly be impoverished.
However, all of this also points to something that often
gets overlooked both about and within philosophy: we need the “core” of
philosophy precisely because it is the entry point and locus of the impersonal
point of view into philosophy. Value
theory leans, rightly, toward the human experience, while M&E lean toward
the impersonal point of view. If the
latter is impoverished, so is the discipline of philosophy as a whole.
Think, for example, of Bertrand Russell’s argument that the
temporal present is an artefact of human psychology, not a feature of time
itself; or David Lewis’s argument that our world is just one of infinitely
many, equally real worlds; or Quine’s argument that the most intimate part of
our experience – the meanings of our thoughts and utterances – are actually
devoid of determinate content because even a perfect scientific observer of
language users would be unable to determine such content; or Mackie’s argument
against the existence of moral properties; or Putnam’s arguments that cognition
can be understood on analogy to computation; and so on.
What all of these landmarks of 20th century
“core” philosophy have in common is the attempt to reconcile the human
perspective with the detached, scientific one.
Similar examples could easily, of course, be produced from the works of
Hume, Nietzsche, Descartes, Locke, Plato, and other notables.
None of this is to argue that the “core” of philosophy is
more valuable or important than any other area.
It is just to argue two things: (1) the “core” remains essential to
philosophical inquiry; and (2) the function of injecting the detached,
impersonal perspective into philosophy is inherently interesting and valuable
precisely because our understanding of ourselves and reality is greatly
enhanced by the attempt to reconcile – or, if that’s not possible,
understanding the gap between – the two perspectives. If we are going to engage properly in the
human project of self-understanding, then the impersonal perspective is
essential (this may sound paradoxical, but I hope to have given reason to think
it in fact isn’t).
So long as we think it is important and valuable to have a
proper understanding of ourselves and the universe we inhabit, the “core” of
philosophy remains something worth doing and something worth pursuing. In short “core”, theoretical philosophy has
value.
This argument is directed not only at academics outside of
philosophy, university administrators, lawmakers, and the general public, but
also at fellow philosophers, some of whom tend to dismiss “core” philosophy for
the usual reasons: the Hawking argument that the questions addressed there
should just be addressed by the sciences; the positivistic one that they all
amount to meaningless speculation; the postmodern one they disguise an
oppressive, harmful ideology; and so on.
On the contrary, I argue, we need half of philosophy to
consist in the regular input of the impersonal perspective into semantics, the
philosophy of mind, ethics, political philosophy, aesthetics, and so on. Without this, there can only be philosophically
impoverished humanistic projects.
These reflections were stimulated in part as a result of some interesting comments by Marcus Arvan (see here)
in which he suggests that we work to raise the public profile and financial
security of the profession of philosophy by emphasizing and selling the
practical, naturalistic, and inter-disciplinary aspects of the field, which, he
argues, are more likely to attract public support and funding, and then use
this funding to support the more theoretical research of the core of
the discipline. This argument is based
on the model provided by the natural sciences which, he argues further, garner
widespread financial and moral support on the basis of their practical
benefits, but which use this support to fund the pure research wings of the
disciplines.
I think this is an interesting suggestion, but I have a
worry, which is that the relationship between the “core” and the more
practical, value theoretic sides of philosophy are not like the relationship
between applied and theoretical science.
In the sciences, as much as there is plenty of jocular put-downs of the
opposing side, the theoreticians and the experimentalists generally respect
each other and recognize the other as engaged in worthwhile, genuinely
scientific work (one side may be *more* valuable, but both are valuable). In Philosophy, there
are too many examples of thinkers accusing their opponents of not even doing
worthwhile work. This is not, contrary
to one narrative one often encounters, just a matter of analytic metaphysicians
telling practical ethicists or Heidegger scholars that what they are doing is “not
philosophy”, but also of thinkers telling analytic metaphysicians that what
they are doing is pointless drivel or actively harmful.
I think we need to stop this and until we do I think that a
strategy such as Arvan’s could inspire increased in-fighting as different philosophical
camps view a renewed focus on practical philosophy as just a grab for an
increased share of limited resources that won’t lead to increased support for “core”
research, since the latter isn't respected by the practical side.
Yes, I am advocating for the importance of the “core” of
philosophy, where I happen to work. I do
not mean to denigrate or complain about other areas of philosophy. As I argue above, we need both sides of the
divide for philosophy to continue to be the special and important discipline
that it is.
No comments:
Post a Comment